forked from maurer/hott-notes
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
notes_week10.tex
425 lines (337 loc) · 17.2 KB
/
notes_week10.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
\documentclass[11pt]{article}
\usepackage[letterpaper]{geometry}
\usepackage{tikz-cd}
\usepackage{amsthm}
\usepackage{proof-dashed}
\input{macros}
%\setlength{\inferLineSkip}{4pt}
\metadata{Muller and Cavallo}{2013/11/18 and 2013/11/20}
\newcommand*{\Void}{\mathsf{0}}
\newcommand*{\Unit}{\mathsf{1}}
\newcommand*{\Bool}{\mathsf{2}}
\newcommand*{\Interval}{I}
\newcommand*{\Izero}{0_I}
\newcommand*{\Ione}{1_I}
\newcommand*{\Iseg}{\mathsf{seg}}
\newcommand*{\ap}{\mathsf{ap}}
\newcommand*{\apd}{\mathsf{apd}}
\newcommand*{\funext}{\mathsf{funext}}
\newcommand*{\isSet}{\mathsf{isSet}}
\newcommand*{\z}{0}
\newcommand*{\s}{\mathsf{succ}}
\newcommand*{\dummy}{\_}
\newcommand*{\triv}{\langle \rangle}
\newcommand*{\comp}{\circ}
\newcommand*{\W}{\mathsf{W}}
\newcommand*{\wrec}{\mathsf{wrec}}
\newcommand*{\wind}{\mathsf{wind}}
\newtheorem{lemma}{Lemma}
\title{15-819 Homotopy Type Theory\\Lecture Notes}
\author{Evan Cavallo and Stefan Muller}
\date{November 18 and 20, 2013}
\begin{document}
\maketitle
\section{Reconsider $\Nat$ in simple types}
As a warmup to discussing inductive types, we first review several equivalent
presentations of the simple type $\Nat$ seen earlier in the course. The
introduction forms for $\Nat$ are $\z$ and $\s(M)$ for any $M: \Nat$.
The elimination form is the recursor $\rec$.
\subsection{Traditional Form}
\[
\begin{array}{c}
\infer[{\Nat}I_{z1}]{\ctx \entails \z : \Nat}{}
\qquad
\hfill
\infer[{\Nat}I_{s1}]{\ctx \entails \s(M) : \Nat}{\ctx \entails M: \Nat}
\\[4ex]
\infer[{\Nat}E_1]
{\ctx \entails \rec[A](M; M_0; x. M_1): A}
{\ctx \entails M : \Nat \qquad
\ctx \entails M_0 : A \qquad
\ctx, x: A \entails M_1 :A}
\end{array}
\]
We include the motive $A$ in the recursor to motivate the dependently-typed
presentation to come although it is not necessary in the simply-typed setting.
The dynamic behavior of $\rec$ is defined by the following $\beta$ rules.
\[\rec[A](\z; M_0; x. M_1) \jdeq M_0\]
\[\rec[A](\s(M); M_0; x. M_1) \jdeq [\rec[A](M; M_0; x. M_1)/x]M_1\]
The recursor on $\z$ returns the base case $M_0$. On $\s(M)$, it substitutes
the recursive result on $M$ for $x$ in $M_1$. The $\eta$ rule states that
any object that ``behaves like'' the recursor is definitionally equal to the
recursor on the appropriate arguments.
\[
\infer[\eta]
{\ctx, y: \Nat \entails N \jdeq \rec[A](y; M_0; x. M_1)}
{[0/y]N \jdeq M_0 \qquad
\ctx, z: \Nat \entails [\s(z)/y]N \jdeq [[z/y]N/x]M_1 : A}
\]
%\subsection{Alternate Form}
%The introduction and elimination rules can be presented in this alternate form:
%\[
%\begin{array}{c}
%\cdot \entails \z : \Nat ({\Nat}I_{z2})
%\qquad
%\hfill
%x: \Nat \entails \s(x) : \Nat ({\Nat}I_{s2})
%\\[4ex]
%M: \Nat, M_0: A, x: A, M_1
%\end{array}
%\]
%% TODO: Help!
\subsection{As elements of the exponential}
The introduction forms of $\Nat$ may be treated as exponentials in the absence
of a context.
\[\cdot \entails \z : 1 \to \Nat \qquad ({\Nat}I_{z3})\]
\[\cdot \entails \s : \Nat \to \Nat \qquad ({\Nat}I_{s3})\]
Note that the type $1 \to \Nat$ is equivalent to the type $\Nat$. There are
two ways to present the elimination form in this format. The first moves the
$\Nat$ on which the recursion is done to the argument position, implying that
$\rec$ has exponential type.
\[
\infer[{\Nat}E_{3a}]
{z: \Nat \entails \rec[A](M_0; x. M_1)(z): A}
{\cdot \entails M_0: A \qquad x: A \entails M_1: A}
\]
This can be presented in a more direct way by omitting the argument.
\[
\infer[{\Nat}E_{3b}]
{\cdot \entails \rec[A](M_0; x. M_1): \Nat \to A}
{\cdot \entails M_0: A \qquad x: A \entails M_1: A}
\]
We can derive rules $\Nat I_{z1}$, $\Nat I_{s1}$ and $\Nat E_1$.
For example,
\[
\begin{array}{c}
\infer{\ctx, M: \Nat \entails \s(M) : \Nat}
{\infer{\ctx, M: \Nat \entails M: \Nat}{\strut} \qquad
\infer[\Nat I_{s3}]{\ctx, M: \Nat \entails \s : \Nat \to \Nat}{\strut}}
\end{array}
\]
\section{$\Nat$-algebras}
We now motivate the idea of $\Nat$-algebras, which are maps of the form
$1 + A \to A$. From the name, one would expect there to be a $\Nat$-algebra
where $A$ is $\Nat$. Indeed, there is.
\[z: 1 + \Nat \entails \case(z; \dummy. \z; x. \s(x)) : \Nat\]
We can write $\case(z; \dummy. \z; x. \s(x))$
above as $\{\dummy. \z; x. \s(x)\}(z)$ or, somewhat abusively,
$\{\z, \s\}(z)$. This gives
\[\cdot \entails \{\z, \s\} : 1 + \Nat \to \Nat\]
as desired. More generally, we can write any $\Nat$-algebra as
$\alpha = \{\alpha_0, \alpha_1\}$ where $\alpha_0 : 1 \to \Nat$ (or,
equivalently, $\alpha_0 : \Nat$) and $\alpha_1: \Nat \to \Nat$. We call
$\alpha_0$ the {\em basis} or {\em pseudo-zero} and $\alpha_1$ the
{\em inductive step} or {\em pseudo-successor}.
In fact, $\{\z, \s\}$ holds a special position among $\Nat$-algebras.
The $\Nat$-algebras form a category and $\{\z, \s\}$ is the initial object
in this category. Recall that this means it has a unique morphism to any other
object in the category. This requires us to define morphisms between
$\Nat$-algebras, which we will call {\em $\Nat$-homomorphisms}. Given two
$\Nat$-algebras, $\alpha : 1 + A \to A$ and $\beta: 1 + B \to B$,
$h: A \to B$ is a $\Nat$-homomorphism if it makes the following diagram commute.
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
1+A \arrow{d}{\alpha} \arrow{r}{1+h} & 1+B \arrow{d}{\beta}\\
A \arrow{r}{h} & B
\end{tikzcd}
\]
The map $1 + h: 1 + A \to 1 + B$ is defined in the natural way:
\[1 + h \defeq \{\dummy. \inl\; \triv; a. \inr\; h(a)\}\]
To show that $\Nat$ is an initial algebra, we must show that for every
$\Nat$-algebra
$\alpha: 1 + A \to A$, there exists a unique $\Nat$-homomorphism $!: \Nat \to A$
such that the following diagram commutes (note that the order of
quantifications expressed in the previous sentence is not inherently clear in
the diagram, and must be considered to get a full understanding of the
diagram.)
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
1+\Nat \arrow{d}{\{\z, \s\}} \arrow[dashed]{r}{1+!} & 1+A \arrow{d}{\alpha}\\
\Nat \arrow[dashed]{r}{!} & A
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Let's consider the requirements on $!$ for the diagram to commute.
\[! \z = \alpha_0 \]
\[! \s(x) = \alpha_1(! x)\]
where the left sides correspond to following the path $! \comp \{\z, \s\}$
and the right sides correspond to following $\alpha \comp 1 + !$. Note that
these two equations match the $\beta$ rules for $\rec$, so we can define
$! \defeq \rec[A](\alpha_0; \alpha_1)$ or simply $! \defeq \rec[A](\alpha)$.
As we see above, the $\beta$ rules for $\rec$ imply
commutation of the diagram. Uniqueness of $!$ follows from the $\eta$ rule
for $\rec$.
It's worth noting that commuting diagrams hide exactly the type of equality
that is being discussed, which is quite
important in HoTT. For $\Nat$, for example, uniqueness of $!$ holds ``on
the nose,'' while, in general, uniqueness may be only up to higher homotopy.
\section{$F$-algebras}
The above discussion can be generalized to any functor $F$. A functor is
a mapping between categories $C$ and $D$. Functors act on objects in a
category and the morphisms between them, i.e. for all objects $X \in C$,
$F(X) \in D$, and for all morphisms $f: X \to Y$ between objects $X$ and $Y$
in $C$, $F(f): F(X) \to F(Y)$.
Functors respect identity and composition:
\begin{enumerate}
\item For every object $X \in C$, $F(\id_X) = \id_{F(X)}$
\item For all morphisms $f: X \to Y$ and $g: Y \to Z$,
$F(g\comp f) = F(g)\comp F(f)$
\end{enumerate}
\cite{WikiFunctor}
For example, $F_{\Nat}(C) \defeq 1 + C$ is a functor. We check that $F_\Nat$
preserves identities and composition. Let $X$ be an object of $C$.
\[F_\Nat(\id_X) = 1 + \id_X = \{\triv, \id_X\}\]
which is indeed an identity
on $1 + X$. Let $f: X\to Y, g: Y \to Z$ be morphisms between objects of $C$.
\[F_\Nat(g \comp f) = 1 + g \comp f = \{\triv, g \comp f\} =
\{\triv, g\} \comp \{\triv, f\} = (1 + g) \comp (1 + f) = F(g) \comp F(f)\]
For any functor $F$, an $F$-algebra is a mapping $F(X) \to X$. Thus,
a $\Nat$-algebra is an $F_\Nat$-algebra. $F$-algebras form categories as
$\Nat$-algebras do. For a functor $F$, objects $A$ and $B$, two $F$-algebras
$\alpha: F(A) \to A$ and $\beta: F(B) \to B$, and a morphism $h: A \to B$,
the following diagram commutes.
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
F(A) \arrow{d}{\alpha} \arrow{r}{F(h)} & F(B) \arrow{d}{\beta}\\
A \arrow{r}{h} & B
\end{tikzcd}
\]
An {\em initial} $F$-algebra is an $F$-algebra $i: F(I) \to I$ such that
for all other $F$-algebras $\alpha: F(A) \to A$, there exists a unique map
$!: I \to A$ such that the following diagram commutes.
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
F(I) \arrow{d}{i} \arrow[dashed]{r}{F(!)} & F(A) \arrow{d}{\alpha}\\
I \arrow[dashed]{r}{!} & A
\end{tikzcd}
\]
There also exists the notion of an $F$-coalgebra, which, dual to the above,
is a map $\alpha: A \to F(A)$. A final $F$-coalgebra is a mapping
$j: J \to F(J)$ such that for all other $F$-coalgebras $\alpha: A \to F(A)$,
there exists a unique map $!: A \to J$ making the following diagram commute.
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
A \arrow{d}{\alpha} \arrow[dashed]{r}{!} & J \arrow{d}{j}\\
F(A) \arrow[dashed]{r}{!} & F(J)
\end{tikzcd}
\]
\begin{lemma}[Lambek]
If $i: F(I) \to I$ is an initial $F$-algebra, then $i$ is an isomorphism.
That is, $F(I) \equiv I$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
To show that $i$ is an isomorphism, we must exhibit an inverse
$i^{-1}: I \to F(I)$
such that $i \comp i^{-1} = \id_I$ and $i^{-1} \comp i = \id_{F(I)}$.
Consider the $F$-algebra $F(i): F(F(I)) \to F(I)$. We now treat $i$ as
homomorphism between the $F$-algebras $F(i)$ and $i$ making this diagram
commute.
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
F(F(I)) \arrow{d}{F(i)} \arrow{r}{F(i)} & F(I) \arrow{d}{i}\\
F(I) \arrow{r}{i} & I
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Since $i$ is an initial $F$-algebra, however, we also have a unique mapping
$!: I \to F(I)$ making the top half of this diagram commute.
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
F(I) \arrow[dashed]{d}{F(!)} \arrow{r}{i} & I \arrow[dashed]{d}{!}\\
F(F(I)) \arrow{d}{F(i)} \arrow{r}{F(i)} & F(I) \arrow{d}{i}\\
F(I) \arrow{r}{i} & I
\end{tikzcd}
\]
There is also a unique mapping from $I$ to $I$, which must be the identity.
This indicates that the mapping $i \comp !$ along the right side of the
diagram must be equal to $\id_I$:
\[i \comp ! = \id_I\]
We also have
\[! \comp i = F(i) \comp F(!) = F(i \comp !) = F(\id_I) = \id_{F(I)}\]
where the first equality follows from the commutativity of the upper half of
the diagram, the second and fourth follow from the properties of functors
and the third follows from the result above.
\end{proof}
This shows that for any functor $F$, the initial $F$-algebra $I$ is a fixed
point of $F$. A dual result can be proven showing that, if $J$ is the final
$F$-coalgebra of a functor $F$, then $F(J) \equiv J$.
\section{Internalizing $\Nat$-Algebras}
Inside type theory, we can define the notion of $\Nat$-algebra as
\[
\mathsf{NatAlg} \defeq \Sigma A{:}\universe.\, ((1 + A) \to A)
\]
We can define the type of $\Nat$-homomorphisms between two $\Nat$-algebras $(A,\alpha)$ and $(B,\beta)$ as
\[
\mathsf{NatHom}(\alpha,\beta) \defeq \Sigma h{:}A \to B.\, (\beta \circ (1 + h) = h \circ \alpha)
\]
The fact that $\nu \defeq \tuple{\Nat}{\{\z, \s\}}$ is initial in the category of $\Nat$-algebras is expressed by the fact that $\mathsf{NatHom}(\nu,\alpha)$ is contractible for all $\alpha$: this means that there exists a $\Nat$-homomorphism from $\nu$ to $\alpha$ which is unique up to higher homotopy.
\section{$\W$-types}
We'd like to be able to take a functor $F$ and define the initial $F$-algebra within HoTT (if one exists). For the class of \emph{polynomial functors}, we can do this using \emph{Brouwer ordinals}, also called \emph{$\W$-types}.
$\W$-types are inspired by the mathematical concept of well-founded induction. In classical mathematics, a partially ordered set $\left< A, < \right>$ is said to be well-founded if every subset of $A$ has a $<$-minimal element (equivalently, there are no infinite descending chains). Well-founded sets are useful because they admit an induction principle:
\begin{quote}
\textbf{Proposition (Well-Founded Induction):} \\
Let $\left<A , <\right>$ be a well-founded set and $P(x)$ be a proposition. If for any $a \in A$ we can prove $P(a)$ by assuming $P(b)$ for all $b < a$, then $P(a)$ holds for all $a \in A$.
\end{quote}
The set of natural numbers $\left< \mathbb{N}, <\right>$ together with its usual ordering is an example of a well-founded set, and the induction principle is the familiar mathematical induction.
Classically, the proof that induction holds goes by contradiction, so this definition is unsatisfactory for a constructive theory. We will instead characterize well-founded sets as those for which we have a (constructive) induction principle.
To better understand what we mean by this, we will define $\W$-types. To form a $\W$-type, we require a type $A$ and a type family $B$ over $A$:
\[
\infer[\W F]
{\ctx \vdash \W x{:}A. B : \universe}
{\ctx \vdash A : \universe & \ctx, x{:}A \vdash B : \universe}
\]
$A$ is the type of \emph{node sorts}. Each node sort represents a different way of forming an element of $\W x{:}A. B$. For example, in the case of the natural numbers, the node sorts are $\z$ and $\s$. We can think of each element of the natural numbers as a tree built from these two sorts of nodes. For example, the numbers 0 through 2 can be represented as
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
\z & \s \arrow{d} & \s \arrow{d} \\
& \z & \s \arrow{d} \\
& & \z
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
Another natural example is the type of binary trees. This type can be defined by two node sorts $\mathsf{node}$ and $\mathsf{leaf}$, with the elements taking the form of trees such as this:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
{}& \mathsf{node} \arrow{dl} \arrow{dr} & \\
\mathsf{leaf} & & \mathsf{leaf}
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
In order to fully specify these two types, we need to have some notion of a node's arity. This is given by the type family $B$. For each node sort $a : A$, $B(a)$ describes the \emph{branching factor} of $a$, the index type to specify the predecessors of a node of sort $a$. For example, the branching factor of the sort $\z$ or $\mathsf{leaf}$ would be $0$, the branching factor of $\s$ would be $1$, and the branching factor of $\mathsf{node}$ would be $1 + 1$. Thus we can write $\Nat$ as $\W x{:}\Bool. \caseif(x;0;1)$, where $\ttsym$ represents $\z$ and $\ffsym$ represents $\s$.
Now that we have the purposes of $A$ and $B$ in hand, we can see how to define the introduction rule for $\W x{:}A. B$.
\[
\infer[\W I]
{\ctx \vdash \sup[a](x.w) : \W x{:}A. B}
{a : A & x{:}B(a) \vdash w : \W x{:}A. B}
\]
In other words, in order to construct a node of sort $a$, we must give an element $\W x{:}A. B$ for each predecessor as specified by the branching factor $B(a)$. Note that when $B(a)$ is $0$ we can construct a new node without any predecessor information. For example, we can construct elements of the naturals as follows:
\begin{align*}
\overline{0} &\defeq \sup[\ttsym](x.\abort{\W x{:}\Bool. \caseif(x;0;1)}(x)) \\
\overline{1} &\defeq \sup[\ffsym](\dummy.\overline{0}) \\
\overline{2} &\defeq \sup[\ffsym](\dummy.\overline{1})
\end{align*}
The recursor for $\W x{:}A. B$ follows the idea of well-founded recursion: in order to define the result of a function $f$ on an element $w : \W x{:}A. B$, we can assume we've already computed $f$ for all of $w$'s predecessors.
\[
\infer[\W R]
{\ctx, z : \W x{:}A.B \vdash \wrec[C](a,r.M)(z) : C}
{\ctx \vdash C : \universe & \ctx, a : A, r : B(a) \to C \vdash M : C}
\]
In the hypothesis, we assume that we are dealing with a node of type $a$ and that we have the value $r(b)$ for each $b : B(a)$ indexing a predecessor. We use this information to construct the value $M$ of the recursor at the current node. The recursor comes with the compuation rule
\[
\wrec[C](a,r.M)(\sup[a](w)) \jdeq [a,\lambda z. \wrec[C](a,r.M)(w(z))/a,r]M
\]
which, as expected, gives the value of $\wrec[C](a,r.M)$ on $\sup[a](w)$ in terms of the value on each predecessor $w(z)$ for $z : B(a)$.
The dependent eliminator has a similar form, expressing the idea of well-founded induction.
\[
\infer[\W E]
{\ctx, z : \W x{:}A.B \vdash \wind[x.P](a,p,h.M) : P(z)}
{\ctx, z : \W x{:}A.B \vdash P : \universe &
\ctx, a{:}A, p : B(a) \to \W x{:}A.B, h : \prod_{b : B(a)} P(p(b))
\vdash M : P(\sup[a](p))}
\]
Here, in order to formulate the hypothesis, we need to assume the additional data $p : B(a) \to \W x{:}A.B$ which gives us the predecessors of the element we are considering. The computation rule takes the form
\[
\wind[x.P](a,p,h.M)(\sup[a](w)) = [a,w,\lambda z. \wind[x.P](a,p,h.M)(w(z))/a,p,h]M
\]
In general, we can only assert that this computation rule holds propositionally.
Each $\W$-type determines a functor, in particular a \emph{polynomial functor}. This is a functor of the form $F(X) = \Sigma a{:}A. (B(a) \to X)$ for some type $A$ and type family $B$. We can see that the $\W$-type $\W x{:}A.B$ defines an $F$-algebra where $F(X) \defeq \Sigma a{:}A. (B(a) \to X)$: we have $\lambda \tuple{a}{w}. \sup[a](w) : F(X) \to X$. The map $\lambda \tuple{a}{w}. \sup[a](w)$ is in fact an equivalence, and $\W x{:}A.B$ is a homotopy-initial $F$-algebra.
In the case of our $\W$-type definition of $\Nat$, observe that the functor determined by $\W x{:}\Bool. \caseif(x;0;1)$ is $F(X) = \Sigma b{:}\Bool. (\caseif(b;0;1) \to X)$. One can check that $\Sigma b{:}\Bool. (\caseif(b;0;1) \to X) \simeq 1 + X$. Thus, this type satisfies the equation $F(X) = 1 + X$, our original definition of a $\Nat$-algebra.
\bibliographystyle{plain}
\bibliography{hott_references}
\end{document}