-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 152
/
sets.tex
1169 lines (1045 loc) · 45.5 KB
/
sets.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
\input{preamble}
% OK, start here.
%
\begin{document}
\title{Set Theory}
\maketitle
\phantomsection
\label{section-phantom}
\tableofcontents
\section{Introduction}
\label{section-introduction}
\noindent
We need some set theory every now and then. We use Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory
with the axiom of choice (ZFC) as described in \cite{Kunen} and \cite{Jech}.
\section{Everything is a set}
\label{section-sets-everything}
\noindent
Most mathematicians think of set theory as providing the basic
foundations for mathematics. So how does this really work?
For example, how do we translate the sentence
``$X$ is a scheme'' into set theory? Well, we just unravel the
definitions: A scheme is a locally ringed space such that every
point has an open neighbourhood which is an affine scheme.
A locally ringed space is a ringed space such that every stalk
of the structure sheaf is a local ring. A ringed space is
a pair $(X, \mathcal{O}_X)$ consisting of a topological space
$X$ and a sheaf of rings $\mathcal{O}_X$ on it. A topological
space is a pair $(X, \tau)$ consisting of a set
$X$ and a set of subsets $\tau \subset \mathcal{P}(X)$
satisfying the axioms of a topology. And so on and
so forth.
\medskip\noindent
So how, given a set $S$ would we recognize whether it is a scheme?
The first thing we look for is whether the set $S$ is an ordered pair.
This is defined (see \cite{Jech}, page 7) as saying that $S$
has the form $(a, b) := \{\{a\}, \{a, b\}\}$ for some sets $a, b$. If this is
the case, then we would take a look to see whether $a$ is an
ordered pair $(c, d)$. If so we would check whether
$d \subset \mathcal{P}(c)$, and if so whether $d$ forms the collection
of sets for a topology on the set $c$. And so on and so forth.
\medskip\noindent
So even though it would take a considerable amount of work to write
a complete formula $\phi_{scheme}(x)$ with one free variable $x$ in set theory
that expresses the notion ``$x$ is a scheme'', it is possible to do so.
The same thing should be true for any mathematical object.
\section{Classes}
\label{section-classes}
\noindent
Informally we use the notion of a {\it class}. Given a formula
$\phi(x, p_1, \ldots, p_n)$, we call
$$
C = \{x : \phi(x, p_1, \ldots, p_n)\}
$$
a {\it class}. A class is easier to manipulate than the formula
that defines it, but it is not strictly speaking a mathematical
object. For example, if $R$ is a ring, then we may
consider the class of all $R$-modules (since after all we
may translate the sentence ``$M$ is an $R$-module''
into a formula in set theory, which then defines a class).
A {\it proper class} is a class which is not a set.
\medskip\noindent
In this way we may consider the category of $R$-modules,
which is a ``big'' category---in other words, it has a
proper class of objects. Similarly, we may consider
the ``big'' category of schemes, the ``big'' category
of rings, etc.
\section{Ordinals}
\label{section-ordinals}
\noindent
A set $T$ is {\it transitive} if $x\in T$ implies $x\subset T$.
A set $\alpha$ is an {\it ordinal} if it is transitive and well-ordered
by $\in$. In this case, we define $\alpha + 1 = \alpha \cup \{\alpha\}$,
which is another ordinal called the {\it successor} of $\alpha$.
An ordinal $\alpha$ is called a {\it successor ordinal} if
there exists an ordinal $\beta$ such that $\alpha = \beta + 1$.
The smallest ordinal is $\emptyset$ which is also denoted $0$.
If $\alpha$ is not $0$, and not a successor ordinal, then $\alpha$ is called
a {\it limit ordinal} and we have
$$
\alpha
=
\bigcup\nolimits_{\gamma \in \alpha} \gamma.
$$
The first limit ordinal is $\omega$ and it is also the first
infinite ordinal. The first uncountable ordinal $\omega_1$
is the set of all countable ordinals.
The collection of all ordinals is a proper class.
It is well-ordered by $\in$ in the following sense: any nonempty set
(or even class) of ordinals has a least element.
Given a set $A$ of ordinals, we define the {\it supremum}
of $A$ to be $\sup_{\alpha \in A} \alpha =
\bigcup_{\alpha \in A} \alpha$. It is the least ordinal bigger
or equal to all $\alpha \in A$.
Given any well-ordered set $(S, <)$, there is a unique ordinal
$\alpha$ such that $(S, <) \cong (\alpha, \in)$; this is
called the {\it order type} of the well-ordered set.
\section{The hierarchy of sets}
\label{section-sets-hierarchy}
\noindent
We define by transfinite recursion $V_0 = \emptyset$,
$V_{\alpha + 1} = P(V_\alpha)$ (power set),
and for a limit ordinal $\alpha$,
$$
V_\alpha = \bigcup\nolimits_{\beta < \alpha} V_\beta.
$$
Note that each $V_\alpha$ is a transitive set.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-axiom-regularity}
Every set is an element of $V_\alpha$ for some ordinal $\alpha$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
See \cite[Lemma 6.3]{Jech}.
\end{proof}
\noindent
In \cite[Chapter III]{Kunen} it is explained that this lemma is
equivalent to the axiom of foundation. The {\it rank} of
a set $S$ is the least ordinal $\alpha$ such that $S \in V_{\alpha + 1}$.
By a {\it partial universe} we shall mean a suitably large set of the form
$V_\alpha$ which will be clear from the context.
\section{Cardinality}
\label{section-cardinals}
\noindent
The {\it cardinality} of a set $A$ is the least ordinal $\alpha$
such that there exists a bijection between $A$ and $\alpha$.
We sometimes use the notation $\alpha = |A|$ to indicate this.
We say an ordinal $\alpha$ is a {\it cardinal} if and only
if it occurs as the cardinality of some set $A$---in other words, if
$\alpha = |A|$. We use the greek letters $\kappa$, $\lambda$
for cardinals. The first infinite cardinal is $\omega$, and in this
context it is denoted $\aleph_0$. A set is {\it countable} if its cardinality
is $\leq \aleph_0$. If $\alpha$ is an ordinal, then we denote
$\alpha^+$ the least cardinal $> \alpha$. You can use this to
define $\aleph_1 = \aleph_0^+$, $\aleph_2 = \aleph_1^+$, etc, and
in fact you can define $\aleph_\alpha$ for any ordinal $\alpha$ by
transfinite recursion. We note the equality $\aleph_1 = \omega_1$.
\medskip\noindent
The {\it addition} of cardinals $\kappa, \lambda$
is denoted $\kappa \oplus \lambda$; it is the cardinality of
$\kappa \amalg \lambda$. The {\it multiplication} of cardinals
$\kappa, \lambda$ is denoted $\kappa \otimes \lambda$; it is the
cardinality of $\kappa \times \lambda$. If
$\kappa$ and $\lambda$ are infinite cardinals, then
$\kappa \oplus \lambda = \kappa \otimes \lambda = \max(\kappa, \lambda)$.
The {\it exponentiation}
of cardinals $\kappa, \lambda$ is denoted $\kappa^\lambda$; it is
the cardinality of the set of (set) maps from $\lambda$ to $\kappa$.
Given any set $K$ of cardinals, the {\it supremum} of $K$
is $\sup_{\kappa \in K} \kappa = \bigcup_{\kappa \in K} \kappa$,
which is also a cardinal.
\section{Cofinality}
\label{section-cofinality}
\noindent
A {\it cofinal subset} $S$ of a well-ordered set $T$ is a subset
$S \subset T$ such that $\forall t \in T \exists s\in S (t \leq s)$.
Note that a subset of a well-ordered set is a well-ordered set
(with induced ordering). Given an ordinal $\alpha$, the {\it cofinality}
$\text{cf}(\alpha)$ of $\alpha$ is the least ordinal $\beta$
which occurs as the order type of some cofinal subset of $\alpha$.
The cofinality of an ordinal is always a cardinal.
Hence alternatively we can define the cofinality of
$\alpha$ as the least cardinality of a cofinal subset of $\alpha$.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-map-from-set-lifts}
Suppose that $T = \colim_{\alpha < \beta} T_\alpha$
is a colimit of sets indexed by ordinals less than a given ordinal $\beta$.
Suppose that $\varphi : S \to T$ is a map of sets.
Then $\varphi$ lifts to a map into $T_\alpha$ for some $\alpha < \beta$
provided that $\beta$ is not a limit of ordinals indexed by $S$,
in other words, if $\beta$ is an ordinal with $\text{cf}(\beta) > |S|$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
For each element $s \in S$ pick a $\alpha_s < \beta$ and an element
$t_s \in T_{\alpha_s}$ which maps to $\varphi(s)$ in $T$.
By assumption $\alpha = \sup_{s \in S} \alpha_s$ is strictly smaller
than $\beta$. Hence the map $\varphi_\alpha : S \to T_\alpha$
which assigns to $s$ the image of $t_s$ in $T_\alpha$ is a solution.
\end{proof}
\noindent
The following is essentially Grothendieck's argument for the existence
of ordinals with arbitrarily large cofinality which he used to prove
the existence of enough injectives in certain abelian categories, see
\cite{Tohoku}.
\begin{proposition}
\label{proposition-exist-ordinals-large-cofinality}
Let $\kappa$ be a cardinal. Then there exists an ordinal
whose cofinality is bigger than $\kappa$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
If $\kappa$ is finite, then $\omega = \text{cf}(\omega)$ works.
Let us thus assume that $\kappa$ is infinite.
Consider the smallest ordinal $\alpha$ whose cardinality is strictly greater
than $\kappa$. We claim that $\text{cf}(\alpha) > \kappa$.
Note that $\alpha$ is a limit ordinal, since if $\alpha = \beta + 1$, then
$|\alpha| = |\beta|$ (because $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are infinite) and
this contradicts the minimality of $\alpha$. (Of course $\alpha$ is also
a cardinal, but we do not need this.) To get a contradiction
suppose $S \subset \alpha$ is a cofinal
subset with $|S| \leq \kappa$. For $\beta \in S$, i.e., $\beta < \alpha$,
we have $|\beta| \leq \kappa$ by minimality of $\alpha$. As $\alpha$ is
a limit ordinal and $S$ cofinal in $\alpha$ we obtain
$\alpha = \bigcup_{\beta \in S} \beta$. Hence
$|\alpha| \leq |S| \otimes \kappa \leq \kappa \otimes \kappa \leq \kappa$
which is a contradiction with our choice of $\alpha$.
\end{proof}
\section{Reflection principle}
\label{section-reflection-principle}
\noindent
Some of this material is in the chapter of \cite{Kunen} called
``Easy consistency proofs''.
\medskip\noindent
Let $\phi(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$ be a formula of set theory.
Let us use the convention that this notation implies that
all the free variables in $\phi$ occur among $x_1, \ldots, x_n$.
Let $M$ be a set.
The formula $\phi^M(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$ is the
formula obtained from $\phi(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$ by replacing all the
$\forall x$ and $\exists x$ by $\forall x\in M$ and $\exists x\in M$,
respectively. So the formula
$\phi(x_1, x_2) = \exists x (x\in x_1 \wedge x\in x_2)$
is turned into
$\phi^M(x_1, x_2) = \exists x \in M (x\in x_1 \wedge x\in x_2)$.
The formula $\phi^M$ is called the {\it relativization of $\phi$
to $M$}.
\begin{theorem}
\label{theorem-reflection-principle}
Suppose given $\phi_1(x_1, \ldots, x_n), \ldots, \phi_m(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$
a {\bf finite} collection of
formulas of set theory. Let $M_0$ be a set.
There exists a set $M$ such that
$M_0 \subset M$ and
$\forall x_1, \ldots, x_n \in M$, we have
$$
\forall i = 1, \ldots, m, \ \phi_i^{M}(x_1, \ldots, x_n)
\Leftrightarrow
\forall i = 1, \ldots, m, \ \phi_i(x_1, \ldots, x_n).
$$
In fact we may take $M = V_\alpha$ for some limit ordinal $\alpha$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
See \cite[Theorem 12.14]{Jech} or \cite[Theorem 7.4]{Kunen}.
\end{proof}
\noindent
We view this theorem as saying the following: Given any
$x_1, \ldots, x_n \in M$ the formulas hold with the bound variables ranging
through all sets if and only if they hold for the bound variables ranging
through elements of $V_\alpha$. This theorem is a meta-theorem because
it deals with the formulas of set theory directly.
It actually says that given the finite list of formulas
$\phi_1, \ldots, \phi_m$ with at most free variables $x_1, \ldots, x_n$
the sentence
$$
\begin{matrix}
\forall M_0\ \exists M, \ M_0 \subset M\ \forall x_1, \ldots, x_n \in M \\
\phi_1(x_1, \ldots, x_n) \wedge \ldots \wedge \phi_m(x_1, \ldots, x_n)
\leftrightarrow
\phi_1^M(x_1, \ldots, x_n) \wedge \ldots \wedge \phi_m^M(x_1, \ldots, x_n)
\end{matrix}
$$
is provable in ZFC. In other words, whenever we actually write down
a finite list of formulas $\phi_i$, we get a theorem.
\medskip\noindent
It is somewhat hard to use this theorem in ``ordinary mathematics''
since the meaning of the formulas $\phi_i^M(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$
is not so clear! Instead, we will use the idea of the proof of the
reflection principle to prove the existence results we need directly.
\section{Constructing categories of schemes}
\label{section-categories-schemes}
\noindent
We will discuss how to apply this to produce, given an initial
set of schemes, a ``small'' category of schemes closed under
a list of natural operations. Before we do so, we introduce the
size of a scheme. Given a scheme $S$ we define
$$
\text{size}(S) = \max(\aleph_0, \kappa_1, \kappa_2),
$$
where we define the cardinal numbers $\kappa_1$ and $\kappa_2$ as follows:
\begin{enumerate}
\item We let $\kappa_1$ be the cardinality of the set of affine opens of $S$.
\item We let $\kappa_2$ be the supremum of all the cardinalities of
all $\Gamma(U, \mathcal{O}_S)$ for all $U \subset S$ affine open.
\end{enumerate}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bounded-size}
For every cardinal $\kappa$, there exists a set $A$ such
that every element of $A$ is a scheme and such that for every
scheme $S$ with $\text{size}(S) \leq \kappa$, there is
an element $X \in A$ such that $X \cong S$ (isomorphism
of schemes).
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Omitted. Hint: think about how any scheme is isomorphic to a scheme
obtained by glueing affines.
\end{proof}
\noindent
We denote $Bound$ the function which to each
cardinal $\kappa$ associates
\begin{equation}
\label{equation-bound}
Bound(\kappa) = \max\{\kappa^{\aleph_0}, \kappa^+\}.
\end{equation}
We could make this function grow much more rapidly, e.g., we could
set $Bound(\kappa) = \kappa^\kappa$, and the result below would still hold.
For any ordinal $\alpha$, we denote $\Sch_\alpha$ the full
subcategory of category of schemes whose objects are elements of
$V_\alpha$. Here is the result we are going to prove.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-construct-category}
With notations $\text{size}$, $Bound$ and $\Sch_\alpha$ as above.
Let $S_0$ be a set of schemes. There exists a limit ordinal
$\alpha$ with the following properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item
\label{item-inclusion}
We have $S_0 \subset V_\alpha$; in other words,
$S_0 \subset \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$.
\item
\label{item-bounded}
For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and any
scheme $T$ with $\text{size}(T) \leq Bound(\text{size}(S))$,
there exists a scheme $S' \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$
such that $T \cong S'$.
\item
\label{item-limit}
For any countable\footnote{Both the set of objects and
the morphism sets are countable. In fact you can prove the lemma with
$\aleph_0$ replaced by any cardinal whatsoever in (3) and (4).} diagram
category $\mathcal{I}$ and
any functor $F : \mathcal{I} \to \Sch_\alpha$, the limit
$\lim_\mathcal{I} F$ exists in $\Sch_\alpha$ if and
only if it exists in $\Sch$ and moreover, in this case,
the natural morphism between them is an isomorphism.
\item
\label{item-colimit}
For any countable index category $\mathcal{I}$ and
any functor $F : \mathcal{I} \to \Sch_\alpha$, the colimit
$\colim_\mathcal{I} F$ exists in $\Sch_\alpha$ if and
only if it exists in $\Sch$ and moreover, in this case,
the natural morphism between them is an isomorphism.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We define, by transfinite induction, a function $f$ which associates
to every ordinal an ordinal as follows. Let $f(0) = 0$.
Given $f(\alpha)$, we define $f(\alpha + 1)$ to be the least
ordinal $\beta$ such that the following hold:
\begin{enumerate}
\item We have $\alpha + 1 \leq \beta$ and $f(\alpha) \leq \beta$.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_{f(\alpha)})$ and any
scheme $T$ with $\text{size}(T) \leq Bound(\text{size}(S))$,
there exists a scheme $S' \in \Ob(\Sch_\beta)$
such that $T \cong S'$.
\item For any countable index category $\mathcal{I}$ and
any functor $F : \mathcal{I} \to \Sch_{f(\alpha)}$, if
the limit $\lim_\mathcal{I} F$ or the colimit
$\colim_\mathcal{I} F$ exists in $\Sch$,
then it is isomorphic to a scheme in $\Sch_\beta$.
\end{enumerate}
To see $\beta$ exists, we argue as follows. Since
$\Ob(\Sch_{f(\alpha)})$ is a set, we see that
$\kappa =
\sup_{S \in \Ob(\Sch_{f(\alpha)})} Bound(\text{size}(S))$
exists and is a cardinal.
Let $A$ be a set of schemes obtained starting with $\kappa$
as in Lemma \ref{lemma-bounded-size}.
There is a set $CountCat$ of countable
categories such that any countable category is isomorphic to
an element of $CountCat$. Hence in (3) above we may assume
that $\mathcal{I}$ is an element in $CountCat$. This means that
the pairs $(\mathcal{I}, F)$ in (3) range over a set.
Thus, there exists a set $B$ whose elements are schemes
such that for every $(\mathcal{I}, F)$ as in (3), if the
limit or colimit exists, then it is isomorphic to an element in $B$.
Hence, if we pick any $\beta$ such that $A \cup B \subset V_\beta$
and $\beta > \max\{\alpha + 1, f(\alpha)\}$, then (1)--(3) hold.
Since every nonempty collection of ordinals has a least element,
we see that $f(\alpha + 1)$ is well defined. Finally, if $\alpha$
is a limit ordinal, then we set
$f(\alpha) = \sup_{\alpha' < \alpha} f(\alpha')$.
\medskip\noindent
Pick $\beta_0$ such that $S_0 \subset V_{\beta_0}$.
By construction $f(\beta) \geq \beta$ and we see that
also $S_0 \subset V_{f(\beta_0)}$. Moreover, as $f$ is
nondecreasing, we see $S_0 \subset V_{f(\beta)}$ is true for any
$\beta \geq \beta_0$.
Next, choose any ordinal $\beta_1 > \beta_0$ with cofinality
$\text{cf}(\beta_1) > \omega = \aleph_0$. This is possible
since the cofinality of ordinals gets arbitrarily large, see
Proposition \ref{proposition-exist-ordinals-large-cofinality}.
We claim that
$\alpha = f(\beta_1)$ is a solution to the problem posed in the lemma.
\medskip\noindent
The first property of the lemma holds by our choice
of $\beta_1 > \beta_0$ above.
\medskip\noindent
Since $\beta_1$ is a limit ordinal (as its cofinality is infinite),
we get $f(\beta_1) = \sup_{\beta < \beta_1} f(\beta)$.
Hence $\{f(\beta) \mid \beta < \beta_1\} \subset f(\beta_1)$ is a
cofinal subset. Hence we see that
$$
V_\alpha = V_{f(\beta_1)} = \bigcup\nolimits_{\beta < \beta_1} V_{f(\beta)}.
$$
Now, let $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$. We define
$\beta(S)$ to be the least ordinal $\beta$ such that
$S \in \Ob(\Sch_{f(\beta)})$. By the above we see
that always $\beta(S) < \beta_1$. Since
$\Ob(\Sch_{f(\beta + 1)}) \subset
\Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$, we
see by construction of $f$ above that the second property of the lemma
is satisfied.
\medskip\noindent
Suppose that $\{S_1, S_2, \ldots\} \subset \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$
is a countable collection. Consider the function
$\omega \to \beta_1$, $n \mapsto \beta(S_n)$. Since the cofinality
of $\beta_1$ is $> \omega$, the image of this function cannot be a
cofinal subset. Hence there exists a $\beta < \beta_1$ such
that $\{S_1, S_2, \ldots\} \subset \Ob(\Sch_{f(\beta)})$.
It follows that any functor $F : \mathcal{I} \to \Sch_\alpha$
factors through one of the subcategories $\Sch_{f(\beta)}$.
Thus, if there exists a scheme $X$ that is the colimit or limit
of the diagram $F$, then, by construction of $f$, we see
$X$ is isomorphic to an object
of $\Sch_{f(\beta + 1)}$ which is a subcategory of
$\Sch_\alpha$. This proves the last two assertions of
the lemma.
\end{proof}
\begin{remark}
\label{remark-how-to-use-reflection}
The lemma above can also be proved using the reflection principle.
However, one has to be careful. Namely, suppose the sentence
$\phi_{scheme}(X)$ expresses the property ``$X$ is a scheme'', then
what does the formula $\phi_{scheme}^{V_\alpha}(X)$ mean?
It is true that the reflection principle says we can find $\alpha$ such that
for all $X \in V_\alpha$ we have
$\phi_{scheme}(X) \leftrightarrow \phi_{scheme}^{V_\alpha}(X)$
but this is entirely useless. It is only by combining two such
statements that something interesting happens. For example suppose
$\phi_{red}(X, Y)$ expresses the property ``$X$, $Y$ are schemes,
and $Y$ is the reduction of $X$'' (see
Schemes, Definition \ref{schemes-definition-reduced-induced-scheme}).
Suppose we apply the reflection principle to the pair of
formulas $\phi_1(X, Y) = \phi_{red}(X, Y)$,
$\phi_2(X) = \exists Y, \phi_1(X, Y)$. Then it is easy to see that
any $\alpha$ produced by the reflection principle has the property that
given $X \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ the reduction of
$X$ is also an object of $\Sch_\alpha$ (left as an exercise).
\end{remark}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-affine}
Let $S$ be an affine scheme.
Let $R = \Gamma(S, \mathcal{O}_S)$.
Then the size of $S$ is equal to $\max\{ \aleph_0, |R|\}$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
There are at most $\max\{|R|, \aleph_0\}$ affine opens of
$\Spec(R)$. This is clear since any affine open
$U \subset \Spec(R)$ is a finite union of principal
opens $D(f_1) \cup \ldots \cup D(f_n)$ and hence the number
of affine opens is at most $\sup_n |R|^n = \max\{|R|, \aleph_0\}$,
see \cite[Ch. I, 10.13]{Kunen}. On the other hand, we see that
$\Gamma(U, \mathcal{O}) \subset R_{f_1} \times \ldots \times R_{f_n}$
and hence $|\Gamma(U, \mathcal{O})| \leq
\max\{\aleph_0, |R_{f_1}|, \ldots, |R_{f_n}|\}$. Thus
it suffices to prove that $|R_f| \leq \max\{\aleph_0, |R|\}$
which is omitted.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-size}
Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $S = \bigcup_{i \in I} S_i$ be
an open covering. Then
$\text{size}(S) \leq \max\{|I|, \sup_i\{\text{size}(S_i)\}\}$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Let $U \subset S$ be any affine open. Since $U$ is quasi-compact
there exist finitely many elements $i_1, \ldots, i_n \in I$
and affine opens $U_i \subset U \cap S_i$ such that
$U = U_1 \cup U_2 \cup \ldots \cup U_n$. Thus
$$
|\Gamma(U, \mathcal{O}_U)|
\leq
|\Gamma(U_1, \mathcal{O})|
\otimes
\ldots
\otimes
|\Gamma(U_n, \mathcal{O})|
\leq \sup\nolimits_i\{\text{size}(S_i)\}
$$
Moreover, it shows that the set of affine opens of $S$ has
cardinality less than or equal to the cardinality of the set
$$
\coprod_{n \in \omega}
\coprod_{i_1, \ldots, i_n \in I}
\{\text{affine opens of }S_{i_1}\}
\times
\ldots
\times
\{\text{affine opens of }S_{i_n}\}.
$$
Each of the sets inside the disjoint union has cardinality at most
$\sup_i\{\text{size}(S_i)\}$. The index set has cardinality at most
$\max\{|I|, \aleph_0\}$, see \cite[Ch. I, 10.13]{Kunen}.
Hence by \cite[Lemma 5.8]{Jech} the cardinality
of the coproduct is at most $\max\{\aleph_0, |I|\}
\otimes \sup_i\{\text{size}(S_i)\}$. The lemma follows.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-size-fibre-product}
Let $f : X \to S$, $g : Y \to S$ be morphisms of schemes.
Then we have
$\text{size}(X \times_S Y) \leq \max\{\text{size}(X), \text{size}(Y)\}$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Let $S = \bigcup_{k \in K} S_k$ be an affine open covering.
Let $X = \bigcup_{i \in I} U_i$, $Y = \bigcup_{j \in J} V_j$
be affine open coverings with $I$, $J$ of cardinality
$\leq \text{size}(X), \text{size}(Y)$.
For each $i \in I$ there exists a finite set $K_i$ of $k \in K$
such that $f(U_i) \subset \bigcup_{k \in K_i} S_k$.
For each $j \in J$ there exists a finite set $K_j$ of $k \in K$
such that $g(V_j) \subset \bigcup_{k \in K_j} S_k$.
Hence $f(X), g(Y)$ are contained in
$S' = \bigcup_{k \in K'} S_k$ with
$K' = \bigcup_{i \in I} K_i \cup \bigcup_{j \in J} K_j$.
Note that the cardinality of $K'$
is at most $\max\{\aleph_0, |I|, |J|\}$. Applying
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-size}
we see that it suffices to prove that
$\text{size}(f^{-1}(S_k) \times_{S_k} g^{-1}(S_k))
\leq \max\{\text{size}(X), \text{size}(Y))\}$ for $k \in K'$.
In other words, we may assume that $S$ is affine.
\medskip\noindent
Assume $S$ affine.
Let $X = \bigcup_{i \in I} U_i$, $Y = \bigcup_{j \in J} V_j$
be affine open coverings with $I$, $J$ of cardinality
$\leq \text{size}(X), \text{size}(Y)$.
Again by
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-size}
it suffices to prove the lemma for the products
$U_i \times_S V_j$. By
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-affine}
we see that it suffices to show that
$$
|A \otimes_C B| \leq \max\{\aleph_0, |A|, |B|\}.
$$
We omit the proof of this inequality.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-finite-type}
Let $S$ be a scheme.
Let $f : X \to S$ be locally of finite type with $X$ quasi-compact.
Then $\text{size}(X) \leq \text{size}(S)$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We can find a finite affine open covering $X = \bigcup_{i = 1, \ldots n} U_i$
such that each $U_i$ maps into an affine open $S_i$ of $S$. Thus by
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-size}
we reduce to the case where both $S$ and $X$ are affine. In this case by
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-affine}
we see that it suffices to show
$$
|A[x_1, \ldots, x_n]| \leq \max\{\aleph_0, |A|\}.
$$
We omit the proof of this inequality.
\end{proof}
\noindent
In
Algebra, Lemma \ref{algebra-lemma-epimorphism-cardinality}
we will show that if $A \to B$ is an epimorphism of rings, then
$|B| \leq \max(|A|, \aleph_0)$.
The analogue for schemes is the following lemma.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-monomorphism}
Let $f : X \to Y$ be a monomorphism of schemes.
If at least one of the following properties
holds, then $\text{size}(X) \leq \text{size}(Y)$:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $f$ is quasi-compact,
\item $f$ is locally of finite presentation,
\item add more here as needed.
\end{enumerate}
But the bound does not hold for monomorphisms
which are locally of finite type.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Let $Y = \bigcup_{j \in J} V_j$ be an affine open covering of $Y$
with $|J| \leq \text{size}(Y)$. By Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-size}
it suffices to bound the size of the inverse image of $V_j$ in $X$.
Hence we reduce to the case that $Y$ is affine, say $Y = \Spec(B)$.
For any affine open $\Spec(A) \subset X$ we have
$|A| \leq \max(|B|, \aleph_0) = \text{size}(Y)$, see remark above
and Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-affine}. Thus it suffices to show
that $X$ has at most $\text{size}(Y)$ affine opens. This is clear
if $X$ is quasi-compact, whence case (1) holds.
In case (2) the number of isomorphism classes of $B$-algebras $A$
that can occur is bounded by $\text{size}(B)$, because each
$A$ is of finite type over $B$, hence isomorphic to an algebra
$B[x_1, \ldots, x_n]/(f_1, \ldots, f_m)$
for some $n, m$, and $f_j \in B[x_1, \ldots, x_n]$. However, as
$X \to Y$ is a monomorphism, there is a unique morphism
$\Spec(A) \to X$ over $Y = \Spec(B)$ if there is one,
hence the number of affine
opens of $X$ is bounded by the number of these isomorphism classes.
\medskip\noindent
To prove the final statement of the lemma consider the ring
$B = \prod_{n \in \mathbf{N}} \mathbf{F}_2$ and set $Y = \Spec(B)$.
For every ultrafilter $\mathcal{U}$ on $\mathbf{N}$ we obtain a maximal
ideal $\mathfrak m_\mathcal{U}$ with residue field $\mathbf{F}_2$;
the map $B \to \mathbf{F}_2$ sends the element $(x_n)$ to
$\lim_\mathcal{U} x_n$. Details omitted.
The morphism of schemes $X = \coprod_\mathcal{U} \Spec(\mathbf{F}_2) \to Y$
is a monomorphism as all the points are distinct. However the cardinality
of the set of affine open subschemes of $X$ is equal to the cardinality
of the set of ultrafilters on $\mathbf{N}$ which is
$2^{2^{\aleph_0}}$. We conclude as $|B| = 2^{\aleph_0} < 2^{2^{\aleph_0}}$.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-what-is-in-it}
Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal as in Lemma \ref{lemma-construct-category} above.
The category $\Sch_\alpha$ satisfies the following
properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item If $X, Y, S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$, then
for any morphisms $f : X \to S$, $g : Y \to S$ the fibre
product $X \times_S Y$ in $\Sch_\alpha$ exists
and is a fibre product in the category of schemes.
\item Given any at most countable collection $S_1, S_2, \ldots$
of elements of $\Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$, the coproduct
$\coprod_i S_i$ exists in $\Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and
is a coproduct in the category of schemes.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and
any open immersion $U \to S$, there exists a
$V \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ with $V \cong U$.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and
any closed immersion $T \to S$, there exists an
$S' \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ with $S' \cong T$.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and
any finite type morphism $T \to S$, there exists an
$S' \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ with $S' \cong T$.
\item Suppose $S$ is a scheme which has an open covering
$S = \bigcup_{i \in I} S_i$ such that there exists
a $T \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ with
(a) $\text{size}(S_i) \leq \text{size}(T)^{\aleph_0}$ for all
$i \in I$, and (b) $|I| \leq \text{size}(T)^{\aleph_0}$.
Then $S$ is isomorphic to an object of $\Sch_\alpha$.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and
any morphism $f : T \to S$ locally of finite type such
that $T$ can be covered by at most
$\text{size}(S)^{\aleph_0}$ open affines, there exists an
$S' \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ with $S' \cong T$.
For example this holds if $T$ can be covered by at most
$|\mathbf{R}| = 2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_0^{\aleph_0}$ open affines.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ and
any monomorphism $T \to S$ which is either locally of finite presentation
or quasi-compact, there exists an
$S' \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ with $S' \cong T$.
\item Suppose that $T \in \Ob(\Sch_\alpha)$ is
affine. Write $R = \Gamma(T, \mathcal{O}_T)$.
Then any of the following schemes is isomorphic to a scheme
in $\Sch_\alpha$:
\begin{enumerate}
\item For any ideal $I \subset R$ with completion
$R^* = \lim_n R/I^n$, the scheme $\Spec(R^*)$.
\item For any finite type $R$-algebra $R'$, the
scheme $\Spec(R')$.
\item For any localization $S^{-1}R$, the scheme $\Spec(S^{-1}R)$.
\item For any prime $\mathfrak p \subset R$, the scheme
$\Spec(\overline{\kappa(\mathfrak p)})$.
\item For any subring $R' \subset R$, the scheme
$\Spec(R')$.
\item Any scheme of finite type over a ring of cardinality at most
$|R|^{\aleph_0}$.
\item And so on.
\end{enumerate}
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Statements (1) and (2) follow directly from the definitions.
Statement (3) follows as the size of an open subscheme $U$ of $S$ is
clearly smaller than or equal to the size of $S$.
Statement (4) follows from (5).
Statement (5) follows from (7).
Statement (6) follows as the size of $S$ is
$\leq \max\{|I|, \sup_i \text{size}(S_i)\} \leq \text{size}(T)^{\aleph_0}$
by Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-size}. Statement (7) follows from (6).
Namely, for any affine open $V \subset T$ we have
$\text{size}(V) \leq \text{size}(S)$ by
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-finite-type}.
Thus, we see that (6) applies in the situation of (7).
Part (8) follows from
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-monomorphism}.
\medskip\noindent
Statement (9) is translated, via Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-affine},
into an upper bound on the cardinality of the rings
$R^*$, $S^{-1}R$, $\overline{\kappa(\mathfrak p)}$, $R'$, etc.
Perhaps the most interesting one is the ring $R^*$. As a
set, it is the image of a surjective map $R^{\mathbf{N}} \to R^*$.
Since $|R^{\mathbf{N}}| = |R|^{\aleph_0}$, we see that
it works by our choice of $Bound(\kappa)$ being at least $\kappa^{\aleph_0}$.
Phew! (The cardinality of the algebraic closure of a field
is the same as the cardinality of the field, or it is $\aleph_0$.)
\end{proof}
\begin{remark}
\label{remark-what-is-not-in-it}
Let $R$ be a ring. Suppose we consider the ring
$\prod_{\mathfrak p \in \Spec(R)} \kappa(\mathfrak p)$.
The cardinality of this ring is bounded by $|R|^{2^{|R|}}$,
but is not bounded by $|R|^{\aleph_0}$ in general.
For example if $R = \mathbf{C}[x]$ it is not bounded by
$|R|^{\aleph_0}$ and if $R = \prod_{n \in \mathbf{N}} \mathbf{F}_2$
it is not bounded by $|R|^{|R|}$.
Thus the ``And so on'' of Lemma \ref{lemma-what-is-in-it} above
should be taken with a grain of salt. Of course, if it ever becomes
necessary to consider these rings in arguments pertaining to
fppf/\'etale cohomology, then we can change the function
$Bound$ above into the function $\kappa \mapsto \kappa^{2^\kappa}$.
\end{remark}
\noindent
In the following lemma we use the notion of an fpqc covering which
is introduced in Topologies, Section \ref{topologies-section-fpqc}.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-by-covering}
Let $f : X \to Y$ be a morphism of schemes. Assume there exists an
fpqc covering $\{g_j : Y_j \to Y\}_{j \in J}$ such that $g_j$ factors
through $f$. Then $\text{size}(Y) \leq \text{size}(X)$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Let $V \subset Y$ be an affine open. By definition there exist
$n \geq 0$ and $a : \{1, \ldots, n\} \to J$ and affine opens
$V_i \subset Y_{a(i)}$ such that
$V = g_{a(1)}(V_1) \cup \ldots \cup g_{a(n)}(V_n)$.
Denote $h_j : Y_j \to X$ a morphism such that $f \circ h_j = g_j$.
Then $h_{a(1)}(V_1) \cup \ldots \cup h_{a(n)}(V_n)$ is
a quasi-compact subset of $f^{-1}(V)$. Hence we can find a
quasi-compact open $W \subset f^{-1}(V)$ which contains
$h_{a(i)}(V_i)$ for $i = 1, \ldots, n$.
In particular $V = f(W)$.
\medskip\noindent
On the one hand this shows that the cardinality of the set of
affine opens of $Y$ is at most the cardinality of the set $S$ of
quasi-compact opens of $X$. Since every quasi-compact open of
$X$ is a finite union of affines, we see that the cardinality
of this set is at most $\sup |S|^n = \max(\aleph_0, |S|)$.
On the other hand, we have
$\mathcal{O}_Y(V) \subset \prod_{i = 1, \ldots, n} \mathcal{O}_{Y_{a(i)}}(V_i)$
because $\{V_i \to V\}$ is an fpqc covering. Hence
$\mathcal{O}_Y(V) \subset \mathcal{O}_X(W)$ because $V_i \to V$
factors through $W$. Again since $W$ has a finite covering by
affine opens of $X$ we conclude that $|\mathcal{O}_Y(V)|$
is bounded by the size of $X$. The lemma now follows
from the definition of the size of a scheme.
\end{proof}
\noindent
In the following lemma we use the notion of an fppf covering which
is introduced in Topologies, Section \ref{topologies-section-fppf}.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-bound-fppf-covering}
Let $\{f_i : X_i \to X\}_{i \in I}$ be an fppf covering of a scheme.
There exists an fppf covering $\{W_j \to X\}_{j \in J}$
which is a refinement of $\{X_i \to X\}_{i \in I}$ such that
$\text{size}(\coprod W_j) \leq \text{size}(X)$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Choose an affine open covering $X = \bigcup_{a \in A} U_a$ with
$|A| \leq \text{size}(X)$. For each $a$ we can choose
a finite subset $I_a \subset I$ and for $i \in I_a$ a quasi-compact open
$W_{a, i} \subset X_i$ such that $U_a = \bigcup_{i \in I_a} f_i(W_{a, i})$.
Then $\text{size}(W_{a, i}) \leq \text{size}(X)$ by
Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-finite-type}.
We conclude that
$\text{size}(\coprod_a \coprod_{i \in I_a} W_{i, a}) \leq \text{size}(X)$
by Lemma \ref{lemma-bound-size}.
\end{proof}
\section{Sets with group action}
\label{section-sets-with-group-action}
\noindent
Let $G$ be a group. We denote $G\textit{-Sets}$ the ``big'' category
of $G$-sets. For any ordinal $\alpha$, we denote
$G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$ the full subcategory of $G\textit{-Sets}$
whose objects are in $V_\alpha$. As a notion for size of a $G$-set
we take $\text{size}(S) = \max\{\aleph_0, |G|, |S|\}$ (where $|G|$ and
$|S|$ are the cardinality of the underlying sets). As above we use the function
$Bound(\kappa) = \kappa^{\aleph_0}$.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-sets-with-group-action}
With notations $G$, $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$, $\text{size}$,
and $Bound$ as above. Let $S_0$ be a set of $G$-sets.
There exists a limit ordinal $\alpha$ with the following properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item We have $S_0 \cup \{{}_GG\} \subset \Ob(G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha)$.
\item For any $S \in \Ob(G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha)$ and any
$G$-set $T$ with $\text{size}(T) \leq Bound(\text{size}(S))$,
there exists an $S' \in \Ob(G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha)$
that is isomorphic to $T$.
\item For any countable index category $\mathcal{I}$ and
any functor $F : \mathcal{I} \to G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$, the
limit $\lim_\mathcal{I} F$ and colimit
$\colim_\mathcal{I} F$ exist in $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$
and are the same as in $G\textit{-Sets}$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Omitted. Similar to but easier than the proof of
Lemma \ref{lemma-construct-category} above.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-what-is-in-it-G-sets}
Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal as in Lemma \ref{lemma-sets-with-group-action}
above. The category $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$ satisfies the following
properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The $G$-set ${}_GG$ is an object of $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$.
\item (Co)Products, fibre products, and pushouts
exist in $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$
and are the same as their counterparts in $G\textit{-Sets}$.
\item Given an object $U$ of $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$,
any $G$-stable subset $O \subset U$ is isomorphic to an object
of $G\textit{-Sets}_\alpha$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Omitted.
\end{proof}
\section{Coverings of a site}
\label{section-coverings-site}
\noindent
Suppose that $\mathcal{C}$ is a category (as in
Categories, Definition \ref{categories-definition-category}) and
that $\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$ is a proper class of coverings
satisfying properties (1), (2), and (3) of Sites,
Definition \ref{sites-definition-site}. We list them here:
\begin{enumerate}
\item If $V \to U$ is an isomorphism, then $\{V \to U\} \in
\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$.
\item If $\{U_i \to U\}_{i\in I} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$ and for each
$i$ we have $\{V_{ij} \to U_i\}_{j\in J_i} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$, then
$\{V_{ij} \to U\}_{i \in I, j\in J_i} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$.
\item If $\{U_i \to U\}_{i\in I}\in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$
and $V \to U$ is a morphism of $\mathcal{C}$, then $U_i \times_U V$
exists for all $i$ and
$\{U_i \times_U V \to V \}_{i\in I} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$.
\end{enumerate}
For an ordinal $\alpha$, we set
$\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_\alpha = \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) \cap V_\alpha$.
Given an ordinal $\alpha$ and a cardinal $\kappa$, we set
$\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_{\kappa, \alpha}$ equal to the set
of elements
$\mathcal{U} =
\{\varphi_i : U_i \to U\}_{i\in I} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_\alpha$
such that $|I| \leq \kappa$.
\medskip\noindent
We recall the following notion, see Sites, Definition
\ref{sites-definition-combinatorial-tautological}.
Two families of morphisms, $\{\varphi_i : U_i \to U\}_{i\in I}$ and
$\{\psi_j : W_j \to U\}_{j\in J}$, with the same target of $\mathcal{C}$ are
called {\it combinatorially equivalent} if there exist maps
$\alpha : I \to J$ and $\beta : J\to I$ such that
$\varphi_i = \psi_{\alpha(i)}$ and $\psi_j = \varphi_{\beta(j)}$.
This defines an equivalence relation on families of morphisms
having a fixed target.
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma-coverings-site}
With notations as above.
Let $\text{Cov}_0 \subset \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$
be a set contained in $\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$.
There exist a cardinal $\kappa$ and a limit ordinal $\alpha$
with the following properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item We have $\text{Cov}_0 \subset \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_{\kappa, \alpha}$.
\item The set of coverings
$\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_{\kappa, \alpha}$ satisfies
(1), (2), and (3) of Sites, Definition \ref{sites-definition-site} (see above).
In other words $(\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_{\kappa, \alpha})$
is a site.
\item Every covering in $\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$
is combinatorially equivalent
to a covering in $\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_{\kappa, \alpha}$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
To prove this, we first consider the set $\mathcal{S}$ of all
sets of morphisms of $\mathcal{C}$ with fixed target.
In other words, an element of $\mathcal{S}$ is a subset $T$
of $\text{Arrows}(\mathcal{C})$ such that all
elements of $T$ have the same target. Given a family
$\mathcal{U} = \{\varphi_i : U_i \to U\}_{i\in I}$ of morphisms with fixed
target, we define
$Supp(\mathcal{U}) = \{ \varphi \in \text{Arrows}(\mathcal{C})
\mid \exists i\in I, \varphi = \varphi_i\}$.
Note that two families $\mathcal{U} = \{\varphi_i : U_i \to U\}_{i\in I}$
and $\mathcal{V} = \{V_j \to V\}_{j \in J}$ are combinatorially
equivalent if and only if $Supp(\mathcal{U}) = Supp(\mathcal{V})$.
Next, we define
$\mathcal{S}_\tau \subset \mathcal{S}$ to be the subset
$\mathcal{S}_\tau = \{ T \in \mathcal{S} \mid
\exists\ \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) \ T = Supp(\mathcal{U})\}$.
For every element $T \in \mathcal{S}_\tau$, set
$\beta(T)$ to equal the least ordinal $\beta$ such that
there exists a $\mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_\beta$
such that $T = \text{Supp}(\mathcal{U})$. Finally, set
$\beta_0 = \sup_{T \in S_\tau} \beta(T)$.
At this point it follows that every $\mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})$
is combinatorially equivalent to some element
of $\text{Cov}(\mathcal{C})_{\beta_0}$.
\medskip\noindent
Let $\kappa$ be the maximum of $\aleph_0$,
the cardinality $|\text{Arrows}(\mathcal{C})|$,